Among the European visitors whose observations of early American life found a ready audience was a young émigré who consorted with the leading scholars, jurists, and literati of his day.1 Unaccountably neglected for over a century, Francis Lieber (1798-1872), one of the first university-trained German scholars to migrate to America, served as a bridge between the intellectual and political cultures of Germany, England, and America. While cultivating an astonishing range of activities and interests, Lieber helped lay the foundation of academic political science in America and promoted its practical application to public affairs. His theory of institutional liberty, which attributes the rise of civil liberty to the development of an increasingly integrated complex of self-governing institutions, may be his most original contribution to the political science literature.
Such varied accomplishments alone would be sufficient to commend Lieber to our attention today. But there is a more immediate purpose that animates this introduction to a forgotten American. Francis Lieber also has much to teach us about the moral requisites of a healthy political community. As the author of treatises that were standard college textbooks to an earlier generation, Lieber might once again serve as a bridge, this time a bridge back to our most vital political traditions and a guide to understanding the roots of American liberty. What follows is an examination of the religious and political factors to which Lieber attributed the historical emergence of modern civil liberty.
A Biographical Sketch
Born into a once-prosperous business family in Berlin, Franz (later Francis) Lieber witnessed Napoleon’s entry into Berlin in 1807 and was severely wounded during the Waterloo campaign in 1815.2 As a student leader in the nationalistic Turnerschaft movement, Lieber was imprisoned for his political activities and barred from the universities, although he contrived to win admission to the University of Jena and was awarded a Ph.D. in 1820. His adventurous spirit took him to Greece the following year to join the fight for independence, and then to Italy, where, now somewhat disillusioned, he came under the wing of the historian and diplomat Barthold Niebuhr.
Granted a royal pardon, Lieber returned to Germany in 1823 but was still regarded with suspicion by the authorities, who imprisoned him briefly and thwarted his efforts to secure a livelihood. So in May 1826 he slipped out of the country again, took passage to England, and found a place in the social circle of John and Sarah Austin. After spending a rewarding but impecunious year in London, he agreed to take charge of a new gymnastics school in Boston. The convivial Lieber, who arrived late in June 1827, soon found his way into the affections of New England society.
Combining a jack-of-all-trades inventiveness with a facility for self-promotion, Lieber came to embody a peculiarly American character-type: the entrepreneur or self-made man. Waning public interest in gymnastics and swimming soon gave him time to begin work as an American correspondent for a German newspaper chain and to launch the Encyclopaedia Americana(1829-1833), which became a major early conduit for the transmission of German cultural influences to America.
Afterwards the self-styled “publicist” (the word is one of his many coinages) won the first in a series of academic appointments. From 1835-1856 he occupied the chair in history and political economy at South Carolina College, then the chair in history and political science at Columbia College from 1857-1865, and finally the chair in constitutional history and public law at Columbia Law School from 1865-1872. During the Civil War, he drafted the first code of militry conduct for use in land warfare, which was later incorporated into the Hague and Geneva Conventions.3
Lieber’s work covers a wide range of fields.4 His contributions to penology, international law, and higher education have been acknowledged in the standard histories of those fields.5Subsequent to the Encyclopaedia Americana, Lieber’s larger works include a popular travelogue Letters to a Gentleman in Germany (1834), which includes an account of the campaign against Napoleon; the two-volume Manual of Political Ethics (1838-1839); Legal and Political Hermeneutics6 (1839), which sets forth principles of interpretation and construction in law and politics; Essays on Property and Labour (1841); On Civil Liberty and Self-Government (1853), his major political science treatise; a posthumous collection of his shorter writings, Miscellaneous Writings (two volumes: 1881); and selections from his letters edited by Thomas Sergeant Perry, The Life and Letters of Francis Lieber (1882).
The Character of Lieber’s Political Philosophy
Alan Grimes places Lieber at the transition between “the constitutional and legal approach to an understanding of the nature of the American Union, and the rise of the organic concept of the nation.”
So it was also probably natural that the first of Lieber’s two treatises on politics would concentrate on political ethics. A Bernard Brown has noted,
Another major dimension of Lieber’s thought is theological. Repeated references to God, creation, and Christianity sprinkle the Manual of Political Ethics and, more casually, On Civil Liberty and Self-Government.11 Far from being incidental to the life of society, Christianity holds a central place that justifies the inclusion of religious instruction in public colleges: “The Christian religion is interwoven with all the institutions which surround us and in which we have our social being. The Christian religion has found its way into a thousand laws, and has generated a thousand others. It can no more be excluded than the common law, or our language.”12
Lieber, a professing Episcopalian, adhered to a dynamic view of divine creation, believing that humanity is providentially designed for a higher destiny. A pervading theocentricity is typical of Lieber’s academic writing. While discussing the importance of “calmness of mind” and trust in politics, Lieber casually added: “Great and calm souls look upon their God, who when He created the rivers and the sea, knew that man would invent bridges, boats, and sails; who when he called the earth into existence and placed man upon it, knew that the plough would be contrived in due time.” 13
It was Lieber’s firm conclusion that human nature reaches its fullest amplitude of expression in a state of civilized interdependence—in cultural maturity—rather than primitive isolation. He focused on the dynamic interplay of man’s individuality and his sociality, involving the conjugal union, the family, language, and the institution of property, to explain the rise and progress of civilization. “Man was either made to be stationary or for civilization; a medium is not imaginable. . . . Civilization develops man, and if he is, according to his whole character and destiny, made for development, civilization is his truly natural state, because adapted to and effected by his nature.” 14 Lieber attributed cultural and developmental differences primarily to tractable historical influences and as a rule was wary of invidious racial or biological comparisons.15
Lieber consciously sought to distinguish his views from the dominant German schools of law and politics. He charged that the historical school sacrificed “right and justice, freedom, truth, and wisdom at the shrine of Precedent and at the altar of Fact” while the philosophical school sought “a predetermined type of social development in each state and nation, and in every race, reducing men to instinctive and involuntary beings, and society to nothing better than a bee-hive.” 16 He likened both society and the state to living organisms, especially to the animal body, which he called “a republic of action.” 17 But in describing his ideal of “hamarchy” (cooperative rule), he avoided the totalitarian implications of the organic model by basing it not, “as it is in so many biological analogies, on the centrally directed nervous and muscular system of the animal, but upon the vital generative power of the disparate ‘systems [which] act and produce independently.’ ” 18
Lieber associated the rise of the nation-state in the modern era with the development of autonomous public institutions. “The ancients knew of no nations” that could fuse “many discordant elements into one society.” 19 At best, the ancient city-state (a term Lieber claimed to have coined) permitted a liberty that “consisted mainly in the equal participation of each citizen in government.” By contrast, the modern representative system, which Lieber called “a flower of civilization,” operates in the context of a nationalized society and a socialized population, which gives much greater scope to the protection of the individual and his rights.
Similarly the Middle Ages lacked a true state: that is, “a clearly organized, enlarged political society.”
Later summarizing this argument, Lieber identified three major characteristics of the development of the modern era. The first is “national polity” or the nation-state. The second is “the general endeavor to define more clearly, and to extend more widely, human rights and civil liberty.” 24 The third is the simultaneous flowering of many leading nations, rather than a single imperial hegemon, under the aegis of international law and “in the bonds of one common moving civilization.” 25 Significantly, he believed that “there will be no obliteration of nationalities” in this commonwealth of nations. Internationalization is merely the latest manifestation of an “all-pervading law of interdependence.” 26
Each of these themes converges in Lieber’s theory of institutional liberty. The theory itself developed through several stages of its own: the idea of hamarchy as the ideal form of the jural society in Manual of Political Ethics (1838, 1839); the contrast between “Anglican Liberty and Gallican Liberty” (1849) in an essay by that title; and, most importantly, the long section on institutional liberty in On Civil Liberty and Self-Government (1853).
Nationalism
The character of institutional liberty is easiest to grasp by starting with Lieber’s essay on “Nationalism and Internationalism” (1868), where the concept was unobtrusively integrated into his theory of nationalism. Lieber regarded the nation as the product of a slow, organic growth that merges the people of a given area into a greater whole. As Alan Grimes notes:
-
- This institutional and evolutionary emphasis in Lieber led him to discard the contract theory of the state, holding that the state arose from the social necessities of man’s being. The nation, in Lieber’s conception, was a homogeneous population, in a coherent territory, with a common language, common literature and institutions, possessed of a consciousness of a common destiny. It was this aspect of commonality of culture, of history, of political institutions and of destiny which made a given people in a given place a nation. This organic concept of the nation was certainly far closer to Burke than it was to the contract theorists in America.
The role of nationalism (another term Lieber coined) was clearly delineated in Lieber’s thinking from the first, although it appears to have gone through some stages in its development. In his early Manual of Political Ethics, Lieber attributed the change between ancient and modern times to six factors:
1) Christianity;
2) the barbrian conquest of the Roman empire;
3) the increased size and population of states;
4) printing;
5) the increased importance of taxpayer, science, and industry; and
6) the discovery of America.28
The first of these factors, Christianity, introduced the crucial presupposition of modern civil liberty by emphasizing the importance of individual character apart from birth, fortune, caste or color:
Lieber’s mature views on the subject of nationalism must be discerned in more fragmentary fashion in his last essays. In an early version of his essay on nationalism, Lieber claimed that “the national polity is the normal type of modern government.”
As with his theological predilections, Lieber’s pro-Union sentiments were echoed throughout his more than three decades of scholarly writing. Despite what he called the “national humiliation and suicide” of the ancient Hebrews “before their national government had fully and comprehensively developed itself,” he considered it very significant that “the only monotheistic people, and the people for whom Moses legislated, formed, in the earliest times of history, a nation in the modern sense. The same cannot be said of ancient Egypt.” 35
Lieber regarded England as the first modern nation and the native land of modern liberty. He dated its origin back to the time of Alfred the Great, its early lawgiver, and maintained that “in her alone liberty and nationality grew apace.” 36 By contrast, the still incomplete process of creating the Italian and German nations had begun only much later when Dante and Luther each raised his native dialect to the dignity of a national tongue.
Turning to the question of whether the early American states formed a distinct nation, Lieber argued that neither the accidents of geography nor the intentions of the crown were determinative. Instead, he began by noting that the American colonists hailed from a country where national institutions were part of their birthright and already displayed considerable expertise in self-government.
The United States were afterward transformed into a national representative republic by the adoption of the Constitution.
Liberty
Lieber opened his 1853 treatise On Civil Liberty and Self-Government with words that, following the collapse of the Soviet empire, resonate very strongly once again. “Our age, marked by restless activity in almost all departments of knowledge, and by struggles and aspirations before the unknown, is stamped by no characteristic more deeply than by a desire to establish or extend freedom in the political societies of mankind.” 42
This is the second modern characteristic: a concern to define and extend human rights and civil liberty. Lieber surveyed the prospect in 1853, describing it as a period of “marked struggle in the progress of civilization” resembling the Reformation in its scope and violence. He invited his readers to accept the task of diffusing civil liberty as the mission assigned their generation. “The love of civil liberty is so leading a motive in our times, that no man who does not understand what civil liberty is, has acquired that self-knowledge without which we do not know where we stand, and are supernumeraries or instinctive followers, rather than conscious, working members of our race, in our day and generation.” 43
Hundreds of political constitutions had been drafted during the first half of the nineteenth century. However short-lived, they would leave roots “which some day will sprout and prosper.” Alluding to the revolutions that had recently convulsed Europe, Lieber remarked that blood “has always flowed before great ideas could settle into actual institutions, or before the yearnings of humanity could become realities.” 44
The most concentrated expression of Lieber’s thought on the subject of civil liberty is found in his essay “Anglican and Gallican Liberty,” published in 1849. Lieber argued that external liberty is an outgrowth of internal freedom. Real freedom is “personal, individual, and relates to the whole being.” Liberty is “granted, guaranteed, and, therefore, generally of a public character.” It is the political expression of this preexisting moral condition of the people. It is a practical result of flourishing, self-governing institutions. “In its ultimate sense, freedom is perfect self-determination: Absolute freedom . . . can be imagined only in conjunction with perfect power. The Almighty alone is perfectly free. To all other beings we can attribute freedom, but only in an approximate or relative sense.” 45
Given its “relative” character, civil liberty is the highest degree of independent action tat is compatible with obtaining those essentials that are the proper objects of public power. Since these objects vary, the character of civil liberty “varies with the different views which men may take, at the various stages of civilization, of that which is essential to man—in other words, of the essentials of humanity and the object and purpose of this terrestrial life.” 46
The classical idea of human nature, represented by Aristotle, treated citizenship as man’s highest estate. Lieber believed that Aristotle’s Politics was confounded by its pre-Christian metaphysics. More positively, Aristotle regarded the presence of certain institutions as indicators of whether liberty existed in a particular state. But even so, neither the Greeks nor the Romans ever succeeded in extending self-government beyond the city-state.
Two distinct ideas of modern liberty have evolved, which may be differentiated as to whether they are centralized or decentralized. Gallican liberty is what Lieber called the kind that is granted by absolute governments, whether the monarchic absolutism of the Bourbon kings and Bonaparte emperors or the democratic absolutism of the French revolutionaries. In either case, the individual is left naked and powerless before the state or the general will.
Anglican liberty, by contrast, is rooted in the habits and loyalties of long-standing communities, as Charles Robson has noted in his summary of Lieber’s views:
Lieber’s reflections on the differences between the decentralized, highly institutionalized Anglican liberty and the centralized, largely unmediated Gallican liberty of Napoleonic France were deepened by first-hand observation of the aftermath of the revolutions which broke out early in 1848. When the news arrived one spring day, the agitated professor dismissed his classes early. He waited impatiently for the end of the school year, then left for Germany late in June. But his hopes for the advent of a liberal regime had been dashed even before his arrival in July.
Much as Lieber wished to see the establishment of Anglo-American institutions in his homeland, he realized that “they presuppose a people well skilled, trained and formed in the politics of liberty.” 53 On leaving Germany for the last time, he sadly wrote his friend Mittermaier in Heidelberg: “I take with me the clear conviction, that Germany cannot be great, strong or happy with her many princes. She could be a great country if united under one government. . . .” 54
Self-Government
At the time Lieber wrote On Civil Liberty and Self-Government (1853) the word “self-government” had not yet come into general use. Although the word is a literal translation of the Greek autonomeia [autonomy], Lieber gave it a much wider application than did the Greeks, for whom “it meant in reality independence upon other states, a non-colonial, non-provincial state of things.” 55 By contrast to the Greeks, who were faced outwardly by foreign states, the English term originated with theologians who used it in an inward, moral sense. “Self-government, the same word [as autonomeia], has acquired with ourselves, chiefly or exclusively, a domestic meaning, facing the relations in which the individual and home institutions stand to the state which comprehends them.” 56 It suggests an internal or moral autonomy or independence from others, including other institutions.
Lieber’s concept of domestic self-government is already evident in the Manual of Political Ethics. Lacking an English word for it, Lieber simply coined one, hamarchy, which he derived “from ama, at the same time, jointly, coöperatingly, and archein, to rule.” 57 He began by defining hamarchy in contrast with “autarchy.”
Institutional Liberty
Lieber apparently dropped both hamarchy and autarchy from his political lexicon by the time he wrote On Civil Liberty and Self-Government, substituting the terms “self-government” and “absolutism.” He wrote that “there is no formula by which liberty can be solved, nor are there laws by which liberty can be decreed, without other aids.” 61 These prerequisites may be acquired only through practice. “How then is real and essential self-government, in the service of liberty, to be obtained and to be perpetuated? There is no other means than by a vast system of institutions, whose number supports the whole, as the many pillars support the rotunda of our capitol.” 62
Lieber defined institution as “a system or body of usages, laws, or regulations of extensive and recurring operation, containing within itself an organism by which it effects its own independent action, continuance, and generally its own farther development. Its object is to generate, effect, regulate, or sanction a succession of acts, transactions, or productions of a peculiar kind or class.” 63 Self-government is one of its chief properties. It “insures perpetuity, and renders development possible.” Otherwise, history “sinks to mere anecdotal chronology. . . . Impulsiveness without institutions, enthusiasm without an organism, may produce a brilliant period indeed, but it is generally like the light of a meteor. That period of Portuguese history which is inscribed with the names of Prince Henry the Navigator, Camoens, and Albuquerque is raiant with brilliant deeds, but how short a day between long and dreary nights!” 64
Lieber extended this idea to include entire systems of institutions. Much of his magnum opus is devoted to a comprehensive list of what he considered to be the constituents of civil liberty (56-255). This lengthy section is introduced by a chapter entitled “Anglican Liberty” (51-55).
Lieber’s characterization of these civil liberties reinforces his view that they depend upon well-articulated and firmly established political and social institutions. The following partial list drawn from “Anglican and Gallican Liberty” and On Civil Liberty and Self-Government is organized simply for the sake of convenience.65
Briefly, the following are protected: persons generally; public and private communication; free production and exchange; religion or worship; lawful opposition to the administration; the minority against the majority; aliens and foreigners; freedom of the people to adopt the government they think best; free choice of residence; freedom of emigration and immigration; and the rights of petition, assembly, bearing arms, and resisting unlawful authority or unlawful demands.
The following are prohibited: extra-governmental power, domination by the central government, unconsented legislation, quartering soldiers in private homes without consent of Parliament, and dictation by one or many.
Finally, the institutional safeguards of liberty include popular control over public funds, self-taxation, judicial review, trial by jury, trial by common courts, due process, publicity concerning political and judicial activities, submission of the army to the legislature, the parliamentary veto, responsibility of ministers and other officers, dependence of the executive on legislative appropriations, restraints on the war-making and peace-making power, independence of the judiciary, the common law principle of precedent, and supremacy of the law.
The chapter on “American Liberty” (256-69) adds the following to the list of Anglican liberties: republicanism, federalism, separation of church and state, political equality, popular elections, separation of powers, judicial review, impeachment, a written constitution, freedom of navigable rivers, and several others.
Lieber maintained that these liberties were still in a “nascent stage” on the European continent, which had gone through “periods of absorbing and life-destroying centralization.” 69 Instead, a prudential balance of local and central initiative is required. It resolves the age-old dilemma of unity and diversity—the problem of the One and the Many—through a fluid mixture of what he called individualism70 and socialism, reason and tradition. Human nature and society should be regarded as both singular and plural:
At the opposite pole from institutional liberty is the fusion of legislative and executive functions that Lieber called, variously, “the power,” “Caesarism,” and “Rousseauism.” He examined the perplexing notion of an “elected despot” in two chapters on “Imperatorial Sovereignty” (374-88) and found the ultimate form of this “democratic absolutism” in the Bonapartist claim that the emperor is the embodiment of the general will. In this ultimate expression of Gallican liberty, Lieber, echoing Edmund Burke, clearly had in mind the French Revolution and its aftermath.72
Concluding Observations
It is easy to read Francis Lieber’s theory of institutional liberty merely as an idealization of the American constitutional tradition. But in the context of the times, it was also a defense of union against the fragmentation that sectional rivalries seemed to threaten.
The sensitivity of Lieber’s position at South Carolina College compelled him to maintain a discreet public silence on the subject of slavery. One consequence was a personal rupture with Charles Sumner that lasted for several years. As the country drifted toward the “sejunction” he dreaded, Lieber chose to move where his greatest sympathies lay, a year before securing another academic appointment. But the move north did nothing to insulate him from the tragedies of the conflict he foresaw.
As an émigré scholar, Lieber was a multiple exile. His attachments were cosmopolitan rather than local. In the end it was the strength of an idea—a commitment to the Union as an ideal—that prevailed over all considerations of place. If indeed it was disunion that had kept Germany so long in thrall, it was natural that Lieber should keenly feel the threat of disunion as an American. His theory of institutional liberty may be regarded, at least in part, as a response to John C. Calhoun’s theory of the concurrent majority.73
The Lieber family, like so many American families, was torn by the war. The talented eldest son, Oscar, died in the service of the Confederacy.74 Two other sons fought—and one was severely wounded—for the Union. In the hour of crisis, Lieber supported policies that could be challenged from the pages of his own books. But his theory was pliant enough to make a place for prudence and the use of temporary expedients.
Lieber was a nationalist of an unusual sort. He consistently encouraged economic free enterprise in his teaching and writings.75 He regarded the rise and fall of nations as simply part of a larger picture. National institutions permit the encouragement of commerce and interdependence among nations. This, in turn, puts absolutism on the defensive, as the chapter on “Gallican Liberty” (279-96) makes clear.
This growing interdependence, then, permits the principle of institutional liberty to operate on a global scale as well as locally. It is this third characteristic of the modern epoch—the flourishing of many nations “in the bonds of one common moving civilization” 76—that seems to have been the greatest encouragement to Lieber’s hopes for the continued growth of liberty.
1 The full list of Lieber’s correspondents is a veritable “Who’s Who” of the literary, political, and academic leaders of his day. Among his major correspondents were J. K. Bluntschli, Henry Clay, Dorothea Dix, Edward Everett, Hamilton Fish, Simon Greenleaf, Gen. Henry Halleck, Samuel Gridley Howe and his wife, James Kent and his son William, Henry Wadsworth Longfellow and his wife, K. A. J. Mittermaier, William H. Prescott, Joseph Story, Charles Sumner, George Ticknor and his wife, Alexis de Tocqueville, and Andrew Dickson White. For a more comprehensive list, see Charles B. Robson, “Papers of Francis Lieber,” Huntington Library Bulletin, 3 (February 1933): 135-55.
2 This account is drawn primarily from Frank Freidel, Francis Lieber: Nineteenth-Century Liberal (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1947). See also Lewis R. Harley, Francis Lieber: His Life and Political Philosophy (New York: AMS Press, 1970 [1899]); and Henry A. Pochmann, German Culture in America: Philosophical and Literary Influences, 1600-1900 (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1961), 125-27.
3 See Richard Shelly Hartigan, Lieber’s Code and the Law of War (Chicago: Precedent, 1983).
4 Apart from news articles, occasional verse, special lectures, topical pamphlets (including pro-Union propaganda), and several major treatises, Lieber also published a study of the Lancastrian system of education; a booklet of German drinking songs; thirteen volumes of his encyclopedia, which was modeled upon Brockhaus’s Konversations-Lexikon; an introduction to Beaumont and Tocqueville’s work on the American penitentiary system, which he also translated; an education plan for Girard College; reminiscences of Barthold Niebuhr; proposals to Congress concerning statistics and an international copyright; remarks on the relation between education and crime; remarks on comparative philology; a study of penology (a term he coined); a study of the vocal sounds of Laura Bridgman, the blind deafmute; and several essays on nationalism and international law.
5 In addition, Lieber’s influence on sociology is noted in Albion W. Small, “Fifty Years of Sociology in the United States,” American Journal of Sociology, 21 (1915-1916): 728-29, note 1; and his place in physical education (along with that of his teacher, Friedrich Jahn) is considered at length in Fred Eugene Leonard, A Guide to the History of Physical Education, 3rd ed., revised by George B. Affleck (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press), 242-47.
6 This work is the subject of James Farr, “Francis Lieber and the Interpretation of American Political Science,” Journal of Politics, 52 (November 1990): 1027-49; and, more recently, A Symposium on Legal and Political Hermeneutics in Cardozo Law Review, 16 (April 1995): 1879-2351, includes a reprinting of the third edition (1880) of Lieber’s text, with some modifications, and ten related articles.
7 Alan Pendleton Grimes, American Political Thought, revised ed. (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1960), 283. Grimes draws primarily from Lieber’s essay “Nationalism and Internationalism” in The Miscellaneous Writings of Francis Lieber, ed. Daniel C. Gilman, vol. 2 (Philadelphia: Lippincott, 1880), 221-43.
8 Francis Lieber, On Civil Liberty and Self-Government, 3rd ed., revised, ed. Theodore D. Woolsey (Philadelphia: J. B. Lippincott, 1877), 300.
9 Bernard Edward Brown, American Conservatives: The Political Thought of Francis Lieber and John W. Burgess (New York: Columbia University Press, 1951), 28. The reference is to one of Lieber’s favorite mottos: “No Right without its Duties, no Duty without its Rights.”
10 D. H. Meyer, The Instructed Conscience: The Shaping of the American National Ethic(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1972), vii. Meyer chose to exclude Lieber because his “concerns and approach clearly [differed] from those of the ordinary textbook writers (147).” See also the chapter on Lieber in Wilson Smith, Professors and Public Ethics: Studies of Northern Moral Philosophers before the Civil War (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1965), 95-110, and a well-integrated treatment of Lieber’s ethics and hermeneutics in Mike Robert Horenstein, “The Virtues of Interpretation in a Jural Society,” Cardozo Law Review, 16 (April 1995): 2273-2304.
11 Lieber’s attention to theology was not unusual at this time. Theodore Woolsey’s Political Science (1877) and Elisha Mulford’s The Nation (1870) show a clear theological orientation. Woolsey, the president of Yale, was much indebted to Lieber’s On Civil Liberty and Self-Government, which Yale adopted as a textbook in the 1850s. Another political scientist at Yale in the early 1870s, who subsequently adopted scientific naturalism, was the Rev. William Graham Sumner. See George M. Marsden, “God and Man at Yale (1880),” First Things, 42 (April 1994): 40. Likewise, John W. Burgess studied theology before he succeeded to the political science chair at Columbia once held by Lieber.
12 “The Necessity of Religious Instruction in Colleges,” in Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 529.
13 Francis Lieber, Manual of Political Ethics, Designed Chiefly for the Use of Colleges and Students at Law, 2nd, revised, ed. Theodore D. Woolsey, vol. 1 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lippincott, 1888), 427. While discussing the importance of a representative form of government, he noted: “In the highest point of view there are no accidents, inasmuch as we imagine Providence overruling the universe in all its elements.” Ibid., vol. 2, 317 note.
14 Manual, vol. 1, 127-28.
15 Charles B. Robson, who did pioneering work in the Lieber Papers in the 1930s and 1940s, noted that “it is possible to charge Lieber with a certain doctrine of racialism; but he neither identified the concept of race with that of a nation nor explained racial characteristics in terms of biological heritage.” C. B. Robson, “Francis Lieber’s Nationalism,” Journal of Politics, 8 (1946): 57.
16 Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 1, 339-40. See also vol. 2, 8-9, 381.
17 Lieber, Manual, vol. 1, 353.
18 C. B. Robson, “Francis Lieber’s Theories of Society, Government, and Liberty,” Journal of Politics, 4 (1942): 241.
19 Manual, vol. 2, 314.
20 Ibid., 315.
21 Ibid., 315 note. Nearly three decades later he wrote: “Centralism . . . may be intelligent and formulated with great precision; but centralism remains an inferior species of government. It is no government of peaceful development, and decentralization becomes necessary as self-government or liberty are longed for and present themselves clearer to the mind of a people waxing in manliness and independence.” Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 226.
22 Manual, vol. 2, 316.
23 Ibid., 318.
24 Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 222, 239.
25 Ibid., 222, 239.
26 Ibid., 241-42.
27 Grimes, op. cit., 283-84. In fact, Lieber was critical of Locke’s contract theory. He probably owed much more to Montesquieu’s idea of the separation of powers and to the influence of Burke on German liberals like Niebuhr and Wilhelm von Humboldt.
28 Manual, vol. 1, 370.
29 Ibid., 372-73.
30 Civil Liberty, 168.
31 Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 225.
32 C. B. Robson, “Francis Lieber’s Nationalism,” Journal of Politics, 8 (1946): 63.
33 Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 229.
34 Manual, vol. 2, 322.
35 Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 230. Enoch Cobb Wines, whose interests included prison reform, had a similar regard for what he called the Hebrew Republic. See E. C. Wines, Commentaries on the Laws of the Ancient Hebrews, with an Introductory Essay on Civil Society and Government. (Philadelphia: William S. & Alfred Martien, 1859 [1853]). The idea that the Israelites had a republican form of government was not a new one. See, for example, the election sermon of Samuel Langdon preached before the General Court of New Hampshire on June 5, 1788, which is reproduced in Ellis Sandoz, ed. Political Sermons of the American Founding Era, 1730-1805 (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1991), 941-67.
36 Ibid., 226. Alfred’s code began with the Ten Commandments.
37 Ibid., 233.
38 Ibid., 235.
39 In the name United States “there are no sovereign people without states, and no states without union, or that are not united states.” At no time were the states independent of each other, in Brownson’s judgment. He held that sovereignty was vested “in the states united, not in the states severally, precisely as we have found the sovereignty of the people is in the people collectively or as a society, not in the people individually. . . .” Alvan S. Ryan, ed. The Brownson Reader (New York: P. J. Kenedy & Sons, 1955), 77.
40 Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 234.
41 Ibid., 237.
42 Civil Liberty, 17.
43 Ibid., 17.
44 Ibid., 18.
45 Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 371.
46 Ibid., 372.
47 Ibid., 372.
48 Ibid., 373.
49 Robson, “Nationalism,” 63-64.
50 Civil Liberty, 53-54.
51 Ibid., 55. Lieber used the term “British liberty” to similar effect in his Manual, vol. 2, 319.
52 Robson, “Nationalism,” 64.
53 The context of this remark in Lieber’s letter to Matilda (August 8, 1848) indicates that he was still optimistic: “No revolution in history was ever so difficult as the German. It is a great misfortune, but natural according to the anteceding circumstances, that an overwhelming majority of the continental people look infinitely more toward France than England. England is shunned as aristocratic, and the whole drift of things here is pre-eminently democratic. This has produced one evil: in the Parliamentary proceedings they have adopted and are daily adopting the French Règlements, instead of the English or American wise rules. However, I doubt very much whether, under all the existing circumstances, the English rules could have been adopted, or if they would have worked well. They presuppose a people well skilled, trained, and formed in the politics of liberty. Yet I must add that the United States is universally mentioned with respect and admiration. This does my heart good.” Thomas Sergeant Perry, ed. The Life and Letters of Francis Lieber (Boston: James R. Osgood, 1882), 218-19.
54 Freidel, op. cit., 248.
55 Civil Liberty, 39 note.
56 Ibid., 39 note.
57 Manual, vol. 1, 352.
58 Ibid., 352-53.
59 See also “Anglican and Gallican Liberty” in Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 380.
60 Manual, vol. 1, 353. Note also the attributes of the state, the “jural society,” the “society of moral beings,” “the society of societies” (162), which Lieber regarded as a distinct moral entity.
61 Civil Liberty, 298.
62 Ibid., 300.
63 Ibid., 300.
64 Ibid., 306.
65 Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 373-75; Civil Liberty, 83-85.
66 Civil Liberty, 375.
67 Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 376
68 David J. McCord, Jr., “Lieber’s Political Ethics,” Southern Quarterly Review, 12 (October 1847): 477.
69 Ibid., 388.
70 Both Lieber and Tocqueville claimed credit for coining the term.
71 Civil Liberty, 260-61.
72 Years later Hannah Arendt acknowledged a similar debt to Burke in her own conception of totalitarianism. “A conception of law which identifies what is right with the notion of what is good for—for the individual, or the family, or the people, or the largest number—becomes inevitable once the absolute and transcendent measurements of religion or the law of nature have lost their authority. And this predicament is by no means solved if the unit to which the “good for” applies is as large as mankind itself. . . . Here, in the problems of factual reality, we are confronted with one of the oldest perplexities of political philosophy, which could remain undetected only so long as a stable Christian theology provided the framework for all political and philosophical problems, but which long ago caused Plato to say: “Not man, but a god, must be the measure of things.” Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism, new edition (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1973), 299.
73 See Freidel, op. cit., 274.
74 James O. Breeden, “Oscar Lieber: Southern Scientist, Southern Patriot,” Civil War History, 36 (1990): 226-49.
75 See “A Letter of Dr. Francis Lieber to D. J. McCord,” in Frederic Bastiat, Sophisms of the Protective Policy, trans. D. J. McCord (New York: Geo. P. Putnam, 1848), 5-14.
76 Miscellaneous Writings, vol. 2, 239.
77 Civil Liberty, 295-96.